The Modes of Constitutional Analysis: Structuralism (Part 7)




Legal Sidebari

The Modes of Constitutional Analysis:
Structuralism (Part 7)

January 13, 2022
This Legal Sidebar Post is the seventh in a nine-part series that discusses certain “methods” or “modes” of
analysis that the Supreme Court has employed to determine the meaning of a provision within the
Constitution. (For additional background on this topic and citations to relevant sources, please see CRS
Report R45129, Modes of Constitutional Interpretation.)
One of the most common modes of constitutional interpretation is based on the Constitution’s structure.
Drawing inferences from the Constitution’s design gives rise to some of the most important relationships
the Constitution establishes—the relationships among the three branches of the federal government
(commonly called separation of powers or checks and balances); the relationship between the federal and
state governments (known as federalism); and the relationship between the government and the people.
Two basic approaches seek to make sense of these relationships.
The first, known as formalism, posits that the Constitution sets forth all the ways in which federal power
may be shared, allocated, or distributed. This approach focuses on the structural divisions in the
Constitution with the idea that close adherence to these rules is required to achieve the preservation of
liberty. An example of the use of this form of structuralism as a mode of interpretation is found in
Immigration and Naturalization Service v. Chadha. In that case, the Court held that one house of
Congress could not by resolution unilaterally curtail the executive branch’s statutory authority to allow a
deportable alien to remain in the United States. The Court examined the Constitution’s structure and
noted that, under the Bicameralism and Presentment Clauses in Article I, Sections 1 and 7, laws with
subject matter that is “legislative in character or effect” require passage by a majority in both houses and
presentment to the President for his signature or veto. The Court wrote: “It emerges clearly that the
prescription for legislative action in [Article I, Sections 1 and 7 of the Constitution] represents the
Framers’ decision that the legislative power of the Federal Government be exercised in accord with a
single, finely wrought and exhaustively considered, procedure.” Viewing the exercise of the one-house
veto in Chadha to be of a legislative nature, the Court concluded that the structural relationships the
Constitution established between the legislative and executive branches forbid the “one-House legislative
veto.” As demonstrated in Chadha, a formalist approach to separation-of-powers questions rejects not
only looking to post-ratification historical practices as a guide for determining constitutional meaning, but
also eschews balancing tests that weigh the degree of interference with one branch’s powers.
Congressional Research Service
https://crsreports.congress.gov
LSB10685
CRS Legal Sidebar
Prepared for Members and
Committees of Congress




Congressional Research Service
2
By contrast, a second form of structural reasoning known as functionalism takes a more flexible approach,
emphasizing the core functions of each of the branches, and asking whether an overlap in these functions
upsets the equilibrium the Framers sought to maintain. An example is the Court’s opinion in Zivotofsky v.
Kerry
. I
n that case, the Court held that the President has the exclusive power to recognize formally a
foreign sovereign and its territorial boundaries, and that Congress could not effectively require the State
Department to issue a formal statement contradicting the President’s policy on recognition. In so holding,
the Court stated that the President should have such exclusive power because the nation must have a
“single policy” as to which governments are legitimate, and that additional pronouncements from
Congress on the issue could result in confusion. The Court thus adopted a functionalist approach by
considering the practical consequences of allocating the power of recognition between the legislative and
executive branches, ultimately concluding that the President alone should exercise that power.
A further illustration of the distinction between formalism and functionalism in a separation-of-powers
case is Morrison v. Olson. In Morrison, the Court upheld against constitutional challenge provisions in the
Ethics in Government Act of 1978 that allowed for appointment of an “independent counsel to investigate
and, if appropriate, prosecute certain high-ranking Government officials for violations of federal criminal
laws.” The Attorney General could remove the independent counsel only for “good cause,” a legal
standard that provided the special prosecutor with significant independence from the President and his
officers. In a 7-1 decision, the Court employed a functionalist approach and held the Act did not violate
constitutional separation-of-powers principles by sufficiently interfering with the President’s executive
authority under Article II. The Court determined the limited nature of the special prosecutor’s jurisdiction
and authority meant that the position did not “interfere impermissibly with [the President’s] constitutional
obligation to ensure the faithful execution of the laws.” Justice Antonin Scalia, the sole dissenter, adopted
a formalist approach, arguing that the majority failed to adhere to the strict allocations of power the
Constitution establishes among the branches of government. Justice Scalia wrote that the independent
counsel provisions deprived the President of “exclusive control” over the exercise of “purely executive
powers” (e.g., investigation and prosecution of crimes) by vesting them in the independent counsel, who
was not removable at will by the President.
Proponents of structuralism note that it is a method of interpretation that considers the Constitution’s
entire text rather than a particular part of it. As a consequence, some proponents argue that structuralist
methods produce clearer justifications for decisions that require interpretation of vague constitutional
provisions and their application to particular factual circumstances than textualism alone. Some argue that
structuralism provides a firmer basis for personal rights than other modes of interpretation, like textualism
or moral reasoning. For example, in Crandall v. Nevada, the Court struck down a state law imposing a tax
on people leaving or passing through the state. The Court inferred an individual right to travel among the
states from the structural relationship the Constitution establishes between citizens and the federal and
state governments. While the Constitution does not specifically provide for a right to travel among the
states, because citizens of the United States might need to travel among the states to exercise other
constitutional rights, the Court inferred a right to travel from the Constitution viewed in its entirety. As a
result, some structuralists argue that this method of interpretation provides a more firm basis to establish
key constitutional rights, like the right to travel, than other modes of constitutional interpretation.


Congressional Research Service
3
Some scholars maintain that interpretations based on structuralism are more difficult for judges to apply
and for citizens to understand than arguments based on other modes of interpretation. In addition, many
believe that determinations about the proper structure established by the Constitution are often subjective.
While Professor Charles Black argued that structure was the most important mode of constitutional
interpretation, another prominent commentator, Professor Alexander Bickel, argued that the approach
provides “no firm basis for personal rights” because personal rights are considered to derive from the
“structure of citizenship” and are therefore “vulnerable to the [government’s] desire for power and its
ability to manipulate the relation between citizen and state.”

Author Information

Brandon J. Murrill

Legislative Attorney




Disclaimer
This document was prepared by the Congressional Research Service (CRS). CRS serves as nonpartisan shared staff
to congressional committees and Members of Congress. It operates solely at the behest of and under the direction of
Congress. Information in a CRS Report should not be relied upon for purposes other than public understanding of
information that has been provided by CRS to Members of Congress in connection with CRS’s institutional role.
CRS Reports, as a work of the United States Government, are not subject to copyright protection in the United
States. Any CRS Report may be reproduced and distributed in its entirety without permission from CRS. However,
as a CRS Report may include copyrighted images or material from a third party, you may need to obtain the
permission of the copyright holder if you wish to copy or otherwise use copyrighted material.

LSB10685 · VERSION 1 · NEW